Mark Neocleous
Dept. of Politics, Brunel University, Uxbridge, UB8 3PH. Email: mark.neocleous
@brunel.ac.uk
HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT. Vol. XXIV. No. 4. Winter 2003
Abstract: This article aims to show the importance of the vampire metaphor to
Marx’s work. In so doing, it challenges previous attempts to explain Marx’s use of the
metaphor with reference to literary style, nineteenth-century gothic or Enlightenment
rationalism. Instead, the article accepts the widespread view linking the vampire to
capital, but argues that Marx’s specific use of this link can be properly understood only
in the context of his critique of political economy and, in particular, the political economy
of the dead.
Towards the end of Volume 1 of Capital, Marx employs one of his usual dramatic
and rhetorical devices: ‘If money comes into the world with a congenital
blood-stain on one cheek,’ he says, then ‘capital comes dripping from
head to toe, from every pore, with blood and dirt’.2 The comment is a
reminder of the extent to which the theme of blood and horror runs through
the pages of Capital. According to Stanley Hyman, there are in Capital two
forms of horror. The first concerns the bloody legislation against vagabondage,
describing the way that agricultural peoples were driven from their
homes, turned into vagabonds and then ‘whipped, branded, tortured by laws
grotesquely terrible, into the discipline necessary for the wage system’. The
second concerns the horrors experienced by people in the colonies, ‘the
extirpation, enslavement and entombment in mines of the aboriginal population
. . . the turning of Africa into a warren for the commercial hunting of
black skins’.3 But to these we might add a third form of horror: the constant
sucking of the blood of the Western working class by the bourgeois class.
This form is nothing less than the horror of a property-owning class that
appears to be vampire-like in its desire and ability to suck the life out of the
working class.
There has in recent years been a mass of literature on the spectre or ghostly
in Marx’s work, heavily influenced by or written in response to Jacques
Derrida’s Specters of Marx. What has not been discussed at any length in this
context has been Marx’s use of the vampire metaphor.4 This is perhaps surprising, first, because of the obvious gothic connection between the ghost and the
vampire — yet even the one sustained attempt to ‘theorize Gothic Marxism’
does not deal with the vampire5 — and, second, because the vampire metaphor
plays a significant role in Marx’s work, a role perhaps even more significant
than the ghostly or spectral. This article aims to show this significance,
first by identifying the extent to which the vampire and associated metaphors
run through Marx’s work, then by outlining some interpretations of Marx’s
use of the metaphor, before pointing out their weaknesses. This will allow a
move towards a fuller understanding of Marx’s vampire metaphor, by situating
it in the very heart of Marx’s work: in his critique of political economy.
Marx’s Metaphor
Terrell Carver has suggested that Marx uses the vampire metaphor three times
in Capital.6 Marx claims that ‘capital is dead labour which, vampire-like,
lives only by sucking living labour, and lives the more, the more labour it
sucks’. He also comments that the prolongation of the working day into the
night ‘only slightly quenches the vampire thirst for the living blood of labour’;
thus ‘the vampire will not let go “while there remains a single muscle, sinew
or drop of blood to be exploited” ’.7 But if one also explores the text for comments
that appear to derive from the vampire motif but fail to mention the
vampire explicitly, one finds a wealth of additional material. Capital ‘sucks
up the worker’s value-creating power’ and is dripping with blood.8 Lacemaking
institutions exploiting children are described as ‘blood-sucking’,
while US capital is said to be financed by the ‘capitalized blood of children’.9
The appropriation of labour is described as the ‘life-blood of capitalism’,
while the state is said to have here and there interposed itself ‘as a barrier to
the transformation of children’s blood into capital’.10
If we take an even greater textual license with Capital, the motif appears
even more apparent. In the chapter on the working day, Marx compares the
historical development of the factory system with other historical forms of
domination, such as Athenian aristocracy, the Norman barons, the American
slave-owners and the feudal corvée. Regarding the latter, he notes that the
legal mechanisms through which peasants performed forced labour on behalf
of landowners could be stretched well beyond the stated number of days. The
example he gives is of Wallachian peasants performing forced labour on
behalf of the Wallachian boyars: ‘For Moldavia the regulations are even
stricter. “The 12 corvée days of the Règlement organique,” cried a boyar,
drunk with victory, “amount to 365 days in the year.” ’11 The source Marx
cites for this quote is É. Regnault’s Histoire politique et sociale des
principautés danubiennes (1855). The ‘Wallachian boyar’ in the text turns out
to be none other than Vlad the Impaler: Vlad Dracula.12
If we extend the textual licence and situate Capital among other texts produced
during its writing, we find even more connections. In the Grundrisse
capital is described as ‘constantly sucking in living labour as its soul,
vampire-like’, or as ‘sucking its living soul out of labour’.13 In the ‘Inaugural
Address of the International Working Men’s Association’, given while he was
in the middle of writing Capital, Marx describes British industry as ‘vampirelike’,
which ‘could but live by sucking blood, and children’s blood too’.14 As
Marx was putting the finishing touches to Volume 1 of Capital, he wrote to
Engels that a number of industries were being ‘called to order’ in a report by
the Children’s Employment Commission: ‘The fellows who were to be called
to order, among them the big metal manufacturers, and especially the vampires
of “domestic industry”, maintained a cowardly silence.’15 At one point
Marx shifts from the vampire to the werewolf, though the implication is the
same: ‘So far, we have observed the drive towards the extension of the working
day, and the werewolf-like hunger for surplus labour, in an area where
capital’s monstrous outrages . . . caused it at last to be bound by the chains of
legal regulations.’16
If one extends such a textual analysis to other major and minor works by
Marx, it is clear that the vampire motif, if not the vampire himself, runs like a
red thread through his work. In The Class Struggles in France he compares
the National Assembly to ‘a vampire living off the blood of the June insurgents’.
17 In The Civil War in France the agents of the French state, such as ‘the
notary, advocate, executor, and other judicial vampires’, are described as
‘blood-suckers’.18 In the Eighteenth Brumaire he comments that ‘the bourgeois
order . . . has become a vampire that sucks out its [the smallholding peasantry’s]
blood and brains and throws them into the alchemist’s cauldron’.19
The Wallachian boyar also makes a reappearance in both the Eighteenth
Brumaire and The Civil War in France.20
The theme of the vampire had also been present in the work of both Marx
and Engels throughout the 1840s. In The Condition of the Working Class in
England, the sociological observations of which filtered through into Marx’s
Capital, Engels had already toyed with the idea of the ‘vampire propertyholding
class’.21 In The Holy Family the two writers comment about a character
of Eugene Sue’s that ‘he cannot possibly lead that kind of life without
sucking the blood out of his little principality in Germany to the last drop like
a vampire’.22 In his unfinished journalism as ‘The Correspondent from the
Mosel’, Marx had planned to write five sections, the fourth (and never written)
of which was to be on ‘The Vampires of the Mosel Region’;23 and in an
essay on the Prussian Constitution of 1849, Marx comments on ‘the Christian-
Germanic sovereign and his accomplices, the whole host of lay-abouts, parasites
and vampires sucking the blood of the people’.24
It is clear, then, that as a metaphor the vampire and its connotations play a
key role in many of Marx’s formulations. The question I wish to address here
is: Why? More specifically, what does Marx mean when he describes capital
as vampire-like? To do so, I begin with a range of possible answers to such
questions and point to their limitations. This will take me to Franco Moretti’s
argument in a major essay on the topic, which I will use as a springboard into a
fuller answer incorporating important aspects of Marx’s critique of political
economy.
Situating the Vampire
One interpretation of Marx’s use of the vampire metaphor might be to suggest
that, in and of itself, the metaphor is merely another literary device employed
by Marx. As is well known, far from being the dry and dull economic tome
some perceive it to be, Capital is, as with all of Marx’s work, full of historical,
philosophical and literary allusions. Robert Paul Wolff comments:
To read the opening chapters of Capital is to be plunged into an extraordinary
literary world, quite unlike anything in the previous, or indeed subsequent,
history of political economy. The text is rich in literary and historical
allusions to the entire corpus of Western culture . . . Marx invokes religious
images, Mephistophelean images, political images. He writes now mockingly
and scornfully, now soberly and with proper professorial seriousness,
now angrily and bitterly. He swings with baffling speed from the most
abstruse metaphysical reflections to vividly sensual evocations of the sufferings
and struggles of English workers against the oppression of their
bosses. At one instant he is a polemicist, writing to the moment. At the next,
he is a pedant, calling down authorities in six languages from twenty centuries
to confirm his etymological tracings and analytical speculations.25
Similarly, Marshall Berman builds his well-known reading of Marx’s ‘modernism’
around the latter’s ‘luminous, incandescent prose’ and ‘brilliant
images’, while Stanley Hyman comments that ‘we get closer to the essential
nature of Capital if we deal with it, not as science, social science, or exhortation,
but as imaginative literature’.26 On this view, one might be inclined to
argue that Marx’s references to the vampire are yet another literary tool in his
armoury — and nothing more. ‘Philosophically the work is not melodrama;
aesthetically it is . . . Marx has yielded to the almost irresistible aesthetic
temptation to prefigure the revolution as drama.’ In this sense ‘Capital is a
dramatic poem, or possibly a dramatic epic . . . If we are not distracted by the
superficial diffusion of the book, its elaborate and energetic logic and its accumulation
of evidence, we see that its concealed structure is mythical.’ As in all
melodrama, the actors become dehumanized—they are dealt with as personifications
of economic categories or, worse, they become other sorts of creatures—
such as vampires.27 Thus Marx’s use of the vampire is merely one of
his ‘occult tropes’, used because he recognized ‘how crucial it was to give an
imaginative account of things’.28
To this interpretation might be added a second one, which situates Marx’s
metaphor in the wider context of nineteenth-century gothic. We know that
Marx enjoyed reading horror stories, and we know that the vampire was a
popular literary form in the nineteenth century. While the best-known novel
of the genre, Bram Stoker’s Dracula, was not published until 1897, after
Marx’s death, the vampire in general had had plenty of coverage prior to that.
James Malcolm Rymer’s Varney the Vampire, for example, serialized the
year before the publication of The Manifesto of the Communist Party,
stretched to 220 chapters over 868 pages.
Cultural and literary studies have come back to the meaning of the gothic in
general and the vampire in particular time and again. Time and again, attention
has focused on the vampire’s alien features—its ‘Otherness’, in the lingua
franca of contemporary theory. Donna Haraway, for example, writes that
‘defined by their categorical ambiguity and troubling mobility, vampires do
not rest easy (or easily) in the boxes labelled good and bad. Always transported
and shifting, the vampire’s native soil is more nutritious, and more
unheimlich, than that.’29 Like the monster in general, the vampire is the ‘harbinger
of category crisis’, resisting easy categorization in the ‘order of
things’. As a form of monster, the vampire disrupts the usual rules of interaction,
occupying an essentially fluid site where despite its otherness it cannot
be entirely separated from nature and man. As simultaneously inside and outside,
the monster disrupts the politics of identity and the security of borders.30
The vampire is a harbinger of ‘category crisis’ because, again as with the
monster in general, he or she represents a form of difference.
Within cultural studies many writers have connected this difference with
the scapegoat, and thus with oppressed and marginalized groups. Following
the connection between the monster and the scapegoat drawn by René
Girard,31 the vampire has been interpreted as the figure of the Jew,32 a
transgressive sexuality either in general33 or in a particular form such as the
homosexual,34 and travellers of all sorts. In particular, it has been argued that the vampire represents the terrifying ‘otherness’ of female sexuality. Tony
Thorne points out that our modern perception of the vampire is distorted by
the (male) influence of Count Dracula himself, but ‘when in the eighteenth
century the blood-sucker first made the transition from village ghoul to literary
protagonist, via Imperial documents and salon gossip, it was as a femme
fatale, a lady, that she was cast’. Until well into the nineteenth century, in the
wake of John William Polidori’s Vampyre (1819), the majority of vampires
were female.35 This gave ideological weight to those who fought against
female sexual emancipation, for the political obsession with blood has ‘been
instrumental in turning any woman who exhibited even the slightest independent
interest in sex into a vampire’.36 More generally, the vampire appears
to be identified with the oppressed and outlawed.
Yet while such answers may have an obvious appeal within, say, cultural
analyses of film or popular literature, they do not quite fit the bill when it
comes to Marx. As Wolff argues, literary style often has ontological presuppositions,
and ‘Marx’s literary style constitutes a deliberate attempt to find the
philosophically appropriate language for expressing the ontological structure
of the social world’.37 Much as Capital may be read as a work of high literary
art, its dominant metaphors and ironic structure serve a deliberate philosophical
and political purpose. The choice of metaphor is thus philosophically and
politically important: through it, Marx aims to make a substantive point about
the social world. Since the vampire is a parasite, Marx could have simply chosen
the term ‘parasite’ or ‘leech’ or something similar; but he chose not to.
Moreover, when he uses the vampire he is hardly using it as a gendered term
or with reference to transgressive sexuality; nor, it must be added, does the
vampire motif appear in his discussions of Judaism in ‘On the Jewish Question’.
Of the many points Marx tries to make about the social world, none of
them can be read as a critique of ‘Otherness’; Marx was hardly an existential
or postmodern cultural theorist avant le lettre.
An alternative way into the subject might be to read Marx’s use of the vampire
metaphor in the context of the kind of writers we know Marx was familiar
with who had also at some point concerned themselves with the vampire. On
this score, Carver situates Marx’s vampire metaphor in the longer history of
interest in the vampire expressed by the eighteenth-century Enlightenment
thinkers. He suggests that Marx’s approach to the vampire ‘was every bit as
rationalist as one would expect, having its roots in the philosophes themselves’.
38 A fair amount of historical and literary evidence might be adduced
for this claim. The eighteenth century was indeed a period of unprecedented
interest in the vampire. The century saw a large number of ‘vampire epidemics’:
in Istria (1672), East Prussia (1710, 1721, 1750), Hungary (1725–30),
Austrian Serbia (1725–32), Silesia (1755), Wallachia (1756) and Russia
(1772).39 The word ‘vampyre’ first entered the English language in the 1680s
(not 1734 as the OED has it) and in the French in the 1690s (becoming a
household word after 1746). It was a familiar word in scholarly debate in Germany
by the 1720s.40 Laurence Rickels estimates that between 1728 and the
early 1840s some forty treatises on vampirism were researched and published
at German and French universities.41 Unsurprisingly, then, the question of the
vampire thus became an important issue for Enlightenment thinkers. As
Christopher Frayling puts it, the age of reason was much perplexed by the
question of vampirism.42
In general, the philosophes’ assumption was that since the vampire was
beyond the bounds of possibility, the vampire itself was either a subject of no
interest or, better still, a subject to be dismissed as a product of ignorant and
unenlightened minds. Voltaire’s entry for ‘Vampires’ in his Dictionnaire
philosophique (1764) begins with a rhetorical and dismissive question:
‘What! Is it in our eighteenth century that vampires exist? Is it after the reigns
of Locke, Shaftesbury, Trenchard, and Collins? Is it under those of
D’Alembert, Diderot, St. Lambert, and Duclos, that we believe in vampires?’
43 In the same vein, the two ‘most eminent physicians’ sent by Maria
Theresa to ascertain the exact nature of the occurrences in Silesia in 1755 concluded
that ‘it was all the result of vain fears, superstitious beliefs, the dark,
disturbed imagination, simplicity and ignorance of the people’.44 In a slightly
different vein, Rousseau concedes that in one sense vampires do indeed
exist — in the minds of those who had attested to their existence — and that
this existence is important because it raises questions concerning how one
interprets the world and, more important, the kinds of authorities that verify
such interpretations. In a letter to Christophe de Beaumont, the Archbishop of
Paris, Rousseau observes that ‘if there is in the world an attested history, it is
just that of vampires. Nothing is lacking; depositions, certificates of notables,
surgeons, curés and magistrates. The proof in law is utterly complete. Yet
with all this, who actually believes in vampires? Will we all be condemned for
not believing in them?’45 For Rousseau, vampires are ‘miraculous’ phenomena
‘attested’ to by all the major authorities, with the corollary that the same
authorities will thus condemn us if we fail to accept the claims for the existence
of vampires. In other words, belief in vampires is evidence of the way
the institutions of authority are legitimized by superstitious and unenlightened
views.
So one source of Marx’s vampire metaphor may well have been the eighteenthcentury
Enlightenment and its main thinkers. But while the unprecedented
eighteenth-century interest and Enlightenment concern with the vampire is
likely to have influenced Marx—and is undoubtedly a more plausible explanation
than the suggestion that Marx’s use of the vampire is linked to his use
of images drawn from the pre-capitalist world46 — as an answer to the question
of why Marx is so interested in the vampire metaphor it is insufficient.
Carver’s suggestion that in using the vampire metaphor Marx was ‘alluding to
the arguments of the philosophes, Rousseau and Voltaire among others, that
the true significance of . . . vampires and other popular superstitions was to
bolster the sacred and secular authorities in society’,47 does not seem to be
borne out by the citations from Marx given above. When Marx uses the vampire
metaphor, he seems to be far from ridiculing it as a superstitious belief.
While he may not be suggesting that the vampire really exists, he uses it as a
metaphor to capture something very real indeed, namely a particular relation
between human beings. It is true that Marx sometimes makes reference to
institutions of authority when using the metaphor. As the examples cited earlier
show, he refers to the French National Assembly as a vampire living off
the blood of the June insurgents, and to other agents of the French state as
‘blood-suckers’ or ‘judicial vampires’. But pace Rousseau, Marx is not suggesting
that the vampire is useful to the authorities by bolstering their position
of interpretive power. Rather, he is clearly suggesting that the authorities
themselves are like vampires. Although Rousseau attempts to situate the vampire
in the wider context of authority in society, his position and Marx’s are by
no means the same. While it may be that ‘Rousseau may have been attracted to
the vampire image because it offered a vivid means of symbolising modes of mutual dependence in society which were not benign’,48 it is not at all clear
that he is doing with the vampire image what Marx was. His vision may have
been of a ‘master–slave dialectic, with teeth’, but it does not appear to have
the same implications as Marx’s.
Now, there is in some Enlightenment thought a little of Marx’s sense. It can
be found, for example, in Voltaire’s entry on vampires in his Dictionary. Voltaire
comments that ‘in both these cities [Paris and London] there were
stock-jobbers, brokers, and men of business, who sucked the blood of the people
in broad daylight; but they were not dead, though corrupted. These true
suckers lived not in cemeteries, but in very agreeable palaces.’ He adds that
‘the true vampires are the churchmen, who eat at the expense of both kings
and people’.49 Similar comments can be found in other eighteenth-century
writings. In England in the1730s The Craftsman presented Walpole and the
past and present directors of the South Sea Company as vampires sucking the
blood of their country;50 and during the 1750s rumours of a bloodsucking
monarch circulated throughout Paris, remaining part of radical-popular folklore
until the revolution of 1789.51 This gets us closer to Marx’s position. Yet,
as I shall now aim to show, it misses what is truly distinctive about Marx’s
position.
Living and Dead Labour
One standard interpretation of the vampire is to see him as representative of a
feudal aristocrat. ‘Vampires are always aristocrats’, we are told.52 Likewise,
Chris Baldick writes that Dracula ‘turns . . . towards an older kind of Gothic
novel in which the bourgeoisie flirtatiously replays its victory over the baronial
despot: Dracula is feudalism’s death warmed up’.53 In contrast to this
view, however, is the far more common view which holds that the vampire is
in fact more representative of capital and a bourgeois class than land and the
aristocracy. This view is most closely associated with Franco Moretti’s essay
on the dialectic of fear. Situating his account in the context of Bram Stoker’s
Dracula (1897), Moretti disregards the conventional account of the vampire
as an aristocrat. Stoker’s Dracula, for example, lacks servants, drives the carriage,
cooks the meals, makes the beds and cleans the castle. He also lacks the
aristocrat’s conspicuous consumption in the form of food, clothing, stately
homes, hunting, theatre-going, and so on. Moreover, the count knows that servants
are unproductive workers. Far from being representative of the aristocratic
class, Dracula’s desire for blood is read by Moretti as a metaphor for
capital’s desire for accumulation. The more he gets, the stronger he becomes,
and the weaker the living on whom he feeds become. Invoking Marx on capital
as vampire, Moretti suggests that ‘like capital, Dracula is impelled towards
a continuous growth, an unlimited expansion of his domain: accumulation is
inherent in his nature’. This vampire is thus ‘capital that is not ashamed of
itself’.54
Moretti’s essay has been hugely influential in developing a reading of the
vampire as capital and thus capital as vampire. Haraway comments that ‘the
vampire is . . . the marauding figure of unnaturally breeding capital, which
penetrates every whole being and sucks it dry in the lusty production and
vastly unequal accumulation of wealth’,55 while Nicholas Rance notes that in
novels such as Rymer’s the metaphor of the vampire is used in precisely the
same sense as in Marx — ‘the Gothic metaphor . . . turns out to be merely a
projection of the ruling capitalist economy’.56 Ken Gelder comments:
the representation of capital or the capitalist as vampire was, then, common
to both Marx and to popular fiction in the nineteenth century. It would not
be an exaggeration to say that this representation mobilised vampire fiction
at this time, to produce a striking figure defined by excess and unrestrained
appetite.57
Put simply, for many writers the vampire is ‘a sanguinary capitalist’.58
There is a great deal of mileage in Moretti’s argument and, given the links
Moretti makes with Marx, his argument has become the standard reading of
the role of the metaphor in Marx’s work. In the context of Marx’s work it is
clear that the vampire as capital is a far more compelling argument than the
vampire as aristocrat, Jew, homosexual or some radical undefined ‘Other’.
Yet Moretti’s argument does not quite paint the full picture. Such a picture, I suggest, can be created only by situating Marx’s vampire metaphor in the context
of his critique of political economy and, in particular, the political economy
of the dead.59
The way to understand Marx’s vampire is less as a nineteenth-century cultural
motif and more as an offshoot of Marx’s preoccupation with the dead.
The social revolution of the nineteenth century can only create its poetry
from the future, not from the past. It cannot begin its own work until it has
sloughed off all its superstitious regard for the past. Earlier revolutions have
needed world-historical reminiscences to deaden their awareness of their
own content. In order to arrive at its own content the revolution of the nineteenth
century must let the dead bury their dead.60
The idea that we must let the dead bury their dead is one Marx adopted from
the Gospel of Matthew (‘Jesus said to him, “Follow me, and leave the dead to
bury their own dead” ’ [8:22]), and was fond of repeating. When Ruge had
written to him despairing of the lack of revolutionary movement in 1843,
Marx replied, ‘Your letter, my dear friend, is a fine elegy, a funeral song, that
takes one’s breath away; but there is absolutely nothing political about it.’ He
adds:
Nevertheless, you have infected me, your theme is still not exhausted, I
want to add the finale, and when everything is at an end, give me your hand,
so that we may begin again from the beginning. Let the dead bury their dead
and mourn them. On the other hand, it is enviable to be the first to enter the
new life alive; that is to be our lot.61
He repeats the point in the The German Ideology.62
The phrase forms part of Marx’s constant reminder that any revolutionary
movement should not be weighed down with the past: as he and Engels put it
in the Manifesto, whereas ‘in bourgeois society . . . the past dominates the
present’, under communism ‘the present dominates the past’.63 But it also
alerts us to the fact that the dead play a significant role in Marx’s work. In the
Preface to the first edition of Capital he comments that ‘we suffer not only
from the living, but from the dead. Le mort saisit le vif! [the dead man clutches
on to the living!]’.64 His reference is to the ‘inherited evils’ that, alongside the
‘modern evils’, oppress us — archaic and outmoded modes of production
with their accompanying anachronistic social and political relations. But it
also suggests that one way to understand the vampire motif is through the role
of the dead in Marx’s critique of political economy.
Fundamental to Marx’s critique of political economy is his understanding
of the dual character of both the commodity and labour. Marx was at pains to
show that the dual nature of labour—as necessary and surplus labour—was
a key component of his argument. In a letter to Engels in August 1867 he comments
that an understanding of the double nature of labour is one of ‘the best
points in my book’.65 We might take these comments to also refer to another
dualism of labour: living and dead labour.
Dismissing the view that capital is something distinct from labour — a
value-producing entity in its own right, for example—Marx argues that capital
is nothing but accumulated labour. His distinction is thus between accumulated
labour and labour per se or, as he often puts it, accumulated labour
versus ‘living labour’. ‘What is the growth of accumulated capital? Growth of
the power of accumulated labour over living labour’; ‘capital does not consist
in accumulated labour serving living labour as a means for new production. It
consists in living labour serving accumulated labour as a means for maintaining
and multiplying the exchange value of the latter.’66 But if the distinction is
between accumulated and living labour, then it makes perfect sense to treat
the former, capital, as ‘dead labour’. Hence ‘the rule of the capitalist over the
worker is nothing but the rule of the independent conditions of labour over the
worker . . . the rule of things over man, of dead labour over living’.67 In capitalist
production, then, ‘living labour appears merely as a means to realize
objectified, dead labour, to penetrate it with an animating soul while losing its
own soul to it’.68 The appropriation by the capitalist of the worker’s productive
powers is a means by which ‘living labour makes instrument and material
in the production process into the body of its soul and thereby resurrects them
from the dead’.69 Inactive machinery is useless—dead—without the active
force of living labour: ‘Iron rusts; wood rots . . . Living labour must seize on
these things [and] change them from merely possible into real and effective
use-values’. In other words, labour must ‘awaken them from the dead’.70
It is this distinction between ‘living labour’ and the ‘dead’ (that is, ‘accumulated’)
labour embodied in capital that provides the initial aptness of the
vampire image.71 But once this aptness is recognized, a host of connected
readings follow. Because the production of surplus value relies on living
labour working on dead labour, the length of the working day is of crucial
political importance. Marx had already pointed out in ‘Wage Labour and Capital’
that ‘capital does not live only on labour. A lord, at once aristocratic and
barbarous, it drags with it into the grave the corpses of its slaves, whole catacombs
of workers who perish in the crises.’72 In Capital this possibility of capital
literally sucking the life out of the workers is fed into the paramount
political question concerning the length of the working day. Capital, with its
desire for endless and incessant accumulation, runs the risk of literally working
the working class to death. ‘By extending the working day, therefore, capitalist
production . . . not only produces a deterioration of human labour-power
by robbing it of its normal moral and physical conditions of development and
activity, but also produces the premature exhaustion and death of this
labour-power itself.’73 Thus the struggle for legal limits on the working day is
nothing less than a struggle through which workers can be saved ‘from selling
themselves and their families into slavery and death’.74
Given the political importance attached to the length of the working day, it
is unsurprising to find that the vampire motif is one of the central tropes
around which the chapter on the working day is structured. Indeed, the three
explicit uses of the vampire metaphor in Capital all occur in the chapter on the
working day. Marx opens the chapter by describing capital as dead labour,
which ‘vampire-like, lives only by sucking living labour’, returns to the point
mid-way through the chapter by commenting on the way the ‘vampire thirst
for the living blood of labour’ prolongs the working day into the night, and
ends the chapter quoting Engels on the unwillingness of the vampire to let go
while there remains a muscle, sinew or drop of blood to be exploited. It is also
in this chapter that the Wallachian boyar makes his appearance (as does the
‘werewolf-like’ hunger for surplus labour and the identification of the desire
to transform children’s blood into capital).
This argument also helps to shed a little more light on the question of alienation
from Marx’s earlier work and the related ‘mystery’ of commodity fetishism.
For the sake of brevity, we can identify two aspects of Marx’s arguments
concerning alienation. On the one hand, he identifies the effects of capitalist
production on the worker. Under capitalism ‘the realization of labour appears
as a loss of reality for the worker, objectification as loss of and bondage to the
object, and appropriation as estrangement, as alienation’.75 In such a system
human beings are alienated from the activity of labour, from the product and
from other human beings and thereby also from themselves. This argument
relies in part on Marx’s related argument concerning the sensuous creature. In
damaging human beings, capital damages them as sensuous creatures—feeling,
experiencing, sensing creatures. ‘To be sensuous, i.e. to be real, is to be an
object of sense, a sensuous object, and thus to have sensuous objects outside
oneself, objects of one’s sense perception. To be sensuous is to suffer.’ At the
same time: ‘Man as an objective being is therefore a suffering being, and
because he feels his suffering, he is a passionate being. Passion is man’s
essential power vigorously striving to obtain its object.’ Passion is thus central
to man’s species-being.76
Marx here reverses Max Stirner’s comments on sensuousness. Marx cites
Stirner as conceiving of sensuousness as a vampire: ‘sensuousness, like a
vampire, sucks all the marrow and blood from the life of man’.77 But for Marx
the reverse is true: sensuousness is the foundation of our species-being; it is
the vampire-like capital that is the death of true sensuousness. Thus only with
the supersession of private property will human sensuousness be able to come
into its own.
The supersession of private property is therefore the complete emancipation
of all human senses and attributes; but it is this emancipation precisely
because these senses and attributes have become human, subjectively as
well as objectively. The eye has become a human eye, just as its object has
become a social, human object, made by man for man. The senses have
therefore become theoreticians in their immediate praxis. They relate to the
thing for its own sake, but the thing itself is an objective human relation to
itself and to man, and vice-versa.78
Only under communism will the human senses be able to be realized in the
fullest sense, and man once more be able to feel like a genuinely living creature,
as opposed to one ruled by the dead (capital). Only vampires (and
necrophiliacs) find anything sensuous in the dead.
On the other hand, Marx’s argument in the 1840s also concerns the capitalist
and the role of capital. ‘The less you eat, drink, buy books, go to the theatre,
go dancing, go drinking, think, love, theorize, sing, paint, fence, etc., the more
you save and the greater will become that treasure which neither moths nor
maggots can consume — your capital.’ Thus although sensuous powers are alienated under the rule of capital, the capitalist is able to recuperate the
estranged sensuality through the power of capital itself:
Everything which the political economist takes from you in terms of life and
humanity, he restores to you in the form of money and wealth, and everything
which you are unable to do, your money can do for you: it can eat,
drink, go dancing, go to the theatre, it can appropriate art, learning, historical
curiosities, political power, it can travel, it is capable of doing all these
things for you.79
As Terry Eagleton points out, capital here becomes a phantasmal body, a
monster which stalks abroad while its master sleeps, consuming the pleasures
the master forgoes. The more the capitalist forswears any sensuous delights,
the more fulfilment he may reap second-hand, so to speak. Thus ‘both capitalist
and capital are images of the living dead’.80
This argument in Marx’s ‘early works’ becomes transformed in Capital
into an account of commodity fetishism. While many writers have highlighted
the ‘metaphysical subtleties and theological niceties’ that run through Marx’s
discussion in the section on the fetishism of the commodity and its secret, and
have consistently pointed to the ‘magical’, ‘spectral’ and ‘spiritual’ dimensions
to his argument, what is relevant here is the fact that the fetish in question
concerns something Marx is describing as dead. Because capital is dead
labour, the desire to live one’s life through commodities is the desire to live
one’s life through the dead. What Marx is doing here is identifying nothing
less than the ‘necromancy that surrounds the products of labour’ (a necromancy
that ‘vanishes as soon as we come to other forms of production’, i.e.
communism).81 The ‘horror’ of fetishism is of course that it conjures up ‘fantastic’—
because ‘transcendent’ and ‘mysterious’—beings.82 But the horror
also lies in the fact that these beings are conjured up out of the dead. On this
basis we might say that the ‘secret’ of commodity fetishism is that it allows
the commodity fetish to partake of the realm of the dead. The trick of fetishism
is thus that it is the inorganic realm of the dead which nonetheless makes
the dead appear alive.83 The vampire metaphor is thus particularly apt in this
context, for the metaphor is in part about the embodiment of the rule of the
dead over the living.84 The vampire is dead and yet not dead: he or she is
‘undead’ in the sense of being a ‘dead’ person who manages to live thanks to
the sensuousness of the living. In being brought back to life in this way the
vampire/commodity comes to rule—through a powerful dialectic of fear and
desire.
I have been arguing that Marx’s use of the vampire metaphor has been hitherto
either neglected or misunderstood. In one sense of course Marx was
indeed employing a rhetorical literary device, one gleaned not from ‘classic
literature’ as many of his allusions are, nor from any of the ‘great thinkers’ he
so often refers to either directly or elliptically, but one which plays on one of
the many popular if irrational beliefs of the time. But this was not simply a rhetorical
device, for Marx uses it to illustrate one of the central dynamics of capitalist
production — the distinction between living and dead labour, a
distinction that picks up on a more general theme in his work: the desire to create
a society founded on the living of full and creative lives rather than one
founded on the rule of the dead. Writing for readers reared on and steeped in
the central motifs of popular literature, Marx thus invoked one of its most
powerful metaphors to force upon them a sense of the appalling nature of capital:
its affinity with death. The vampire, as a ‘monster’, is of course connected
to the root of that term: from monstrare, meaning ‘to show forth’, monstra,
meaning to warn or show, monstrum, meaning ‘that which reveals’, or ‘that
which warns’, and monere, meaning ‘to warn’. The vampire as monster both
demonstrates the capabilities of capital and acts as a warning about it.
NOTES
2 Karl Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Volume 1 (1867), trans. Ben
Fowkes (Harmondsworth, 1976), p. 926.
3 Stanley Edgar Hyman, The Tangled Bank: Darwin, Marx, Frazer and Freud as
Imaginative Writers (New York, 1962), p. 145. The citations are from Capital, pp. 899
and 915.
4 Derrida, for example, subsumes the question of the vampire into the spectre. See
Jacques Derrida, Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the
New International, trans. Peggy Kamuf (London, 1994), p. 155. The literature on the
ghostly/spectral in Marx’s work is now too numerous to list.
5 Margaret Cohen, Profane Illumination: Walter Benjamin and the Paris of Surrealist
Revolution (Berkeley, 1993).
6 Terrell Carver, ‘Making Capital out of Vampires’, Times Higher Educational Supplement,
15 (June 1984); Terrell Carver, The Postmodern Marx (Manchester, 1998),
p. 14.
7 Marx, Capital, pp. 342, 367, 416. The citation within the last of these is from
Engels’ article ‘The Ten Hours Bill’ (1850).
8 Marx, Capital, pp. 716, 926.
9 Ibid., pp. 598, 920.
10 Ibid., pp. 382, 1007.
11 Ibid., p. 348. Engels reiterates the point in Anti-Dühring, trans. Emile Burns (Moscow,
1947), p. 191.
12 Christopher Frayling, Vampyres: Lord Byron to Count Dracula (London, 1991),
p. 84.
13 Karl Marx, Grundrisse, trans. Martin Nicolaus (Harmondsworth, 1973), pp. 646,
660.
14 Karl Marx, ‘Inaugural Address of the International Working Men’s Association’
(1864), in The First International and After, ed. David Fernbach (Harmondsworth,
1974), p. 79.
15 Marx to Engels, 22 June 1867, in Collected Works, Vol. 42 (London, 1987), p. 383.
16 Marx, Capital, p. 353.
17 Karl Marx, The Class Struggles in France: 1848 to 1850 (1850), in Surveys from
Exile, ed. David Fernbach (Harmondsworth, 1973), p. 88.
18 Karl Marx, The Civil War in France (1871), in The First International and After,
ed. Fernbach, p. 215. The ‘First Draft’ of the text also comments on this ‘sucking’ tendency
(p. 249).
19 Marx, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (1852), in Surveys from Exile,
ed. Fernbach, p. 242.
20 Ibid., p. 181; Marx, Civil War in France, p. 219.
21 Frederick Engels, The Condition of the Working Class in England (1845) (London,
1969), p. 264. We have already noted Marx lifting this trope from Engels’ essay on the
English Ten Hours Bill. As well as the comment cited by Marx above, in that article
Engels also describes the system as ‘bloodsucking’. See ‘The Ten Hours Question’ in
Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 10 (London, 1978), pp. 271–2.
22 Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, The Holy Family, or Critique of Critical Criticism
(1845), in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 4 (London,
1975), p. 203.
23 Karl Marx, ‘Justification of the Correspondent from the Mosel’, in Karl Marx and
Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 1 (London, 1975), p. 334.
24 Karl Marx, ‘The New Prussian Constitution’ (1849), in Karl Marx and Frederick
Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 9 (London, 1977), p. 430.
25 Robert Paul Wolff, Moneybags Must Be So Lucky: On the Literary Structure of
‘Capital’ (Amherst, MA,1988), p. 13.
26 Marshall Berman, All That Is Solid Melts Into Air: The Experience of Modernity
(London, 1983), p. 91; Hyman, Tangled Bank, p. 133.
27 Wylie Sypher, ‘Aesthetic of Revolution: The Marxist Melodrama’, Kenyon
Review, Vol. 10 (3) (1948), pp. 431–44, p. 430.
28 Andrew Smith, ‘Reading Wealth in Nigeria: Occult Capitalism and Marx’s Vampires’,
Historical Materialism, 9 (2001), pp. 39–59, pp. 44, 47.
29 D.J. Haraway, Modest_Witness@Second_Millennium.FemaleMan©_Meets_Onco
Mouse™ (London, 1997), pp. 214–15.
30 Jeffrey Jerome Cohen, ‘Monster Culture (Seven Theses)’, in Monster Theory, ed.
Jeffrey Jerome Cohen (Minneapolis, 1996), pp. 3–25; Margit Shildrick, Embodying the
Monster: Encounters with the Vulnerable Self (London, 2002).
31 René Girard, The Scapegoat, trans. Yvonne Freccero (London, 1986), p. 33.
32 For example, Jules Zanger, ‘A Sympathetic Vibration: Dracula and the Jews’,
English Literature in Transition 1880–1920, 34 (1) (1991), pp. 33–45; Ken Gelder,
Reading the Vampire (London, 1994), p. 22.
33 Cynthia A. Freeland, The Naked and the Undead: Evil and the Appeal of Horror
(Boulder, CO, 2000), pp. 123–59.
34 Richard Dyer, ‘Children of the Night: Vampirism as Homosexuality, Homosexuality
as Vampirism’, in Sweet Dreams: Sexuality, Gender and Popular Fiction, ed.
Susannah Radstone (London, 1988).
35 Tony Thorne, Children of the Night: Of Vampires and Vampirism (London, 1999),
pp. 43, 46, 231–3.
36 Bram Dijkstra, Evil Sisters: The Threat of Female Sexuality in Twentieth-Century
Culture (New York, 1996), p. 91; also see Nina Auerbach, Our Vampires, Ourselves
(Chicago, 1995).
37 Wolff, Moneybags Must Be So Lucky, pp. 20, 43, 78–9.
38 Carver, ‘Making Capital out of Vampires’; Carver, Postmodern Marx, pp. 16–18.
39 Frayling, Vampyres, pp. 19, 27.
40 Katharina M. Wilson, ‘The History of the Word “Vampire” ’, Journal of the History
of Ideas, 46 (4) (1985), pp. 577–83.
41 Laurence A. Rickels, The Vampire Lectures (Minneapolis, 1999), p. 15.
42 Frayling, Vampyres, p. 23.
43 M. De Voltaire, A Philosophical Dictionary, Vol. II (London, n.d.), p. 560.
44 Cited in Franco Venturi, Italy and the Enlightenment: Studies in a Comparative
Century, trans. Susan Corsi (London, 1972), pp. 123–4.
45 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, ‘Lettre a C. De Beaumont’, in Oeuvres Complètes, IV
(Paris,1969), p. 987.
46 This is a claim some have made following the work of Taussig. Smith, for example,
claims that ‘Marx’s rhetorical fulcrum . . . relies on an imaginative juxtaposition with
images drawn from the pre-capitalist world’ (Smith, ‘Reading Wealth in Nigeria’, p. 45).
The argument follows Michael Taussig’s work on the occult tropes involved in the culture
and resistance of the subaltern worker, in his The Devil and Commodity Fetishism in
South America (Chapel Hill, NC, 1980). But there is little evidence of the vampire as
opposed to, say, the devil, in these tropes; nor is there any evidence that this was Marx’s
source.
47 Carver, ‘Making Capital out of Vampires’; Postmodern Marx, p. 18.
48 Christopher Frayling and Robert Wokler, ‘From the Orang-utan to the Vampire:
Towards an Anthropology of Rousseau’, in Rousseau After 200 years: Proceedings of
the Cambridge Bicentennial Colloquium, ed. R.A. Leigh (Cambridge, 1982), p. 118;
Frayling, Vampyres, p. 34.
49 Voltaire, Philosophical Dictionary, pp. 560–2.
50 See Vincent Carretta, The Snarling Muse: Verbal and Political Satire from Pope to
Churchill (Philadelphia, 1983), p. 66.
51 Marina Warner, No Go the Bogeyman: Scaring, Lulling, and Making Mock (New
York, 1998), pp. 134–5.
52 Mark Edmundson, Nightmare on Main Street: Angels, Sadomasochism, and the
Culture of Gothic (Cambridge, MA, 1997), p. 20.
53 Chris Baldick, In Frankenstein’s Shadow: Myth, Monstrosity, and Nineteenthcentury
Writing (Oxford, 1987), p. 148. It should be said that this view contradicts
Baldick’s earlier (pp. 128–31) and far more compelling argument concerning the vampire
as representative of capital.
54 Franco Moretti, Signs Taken for Wonders: Essays in the Sociology of Literary
Forms (London, 1983), pp. 90, 91, 94. I ignore here Moretti’s sub-theme concerning
monopoly capital and nationalism, as it is irrelevant to my argument.
55 Haraway, Modest_Witness, p. 215.
56 Nicholas Rance, Wilkie Collins and Other Sensation Novelists (Rutherford, 1991),
p. 60.
57 Gelder, Reading the Vampire, p. 22.
58 David J. Skal, The Monster Show: A Cultural History of Horror (London, 1993),
p. 159.
59 Alonger version of the argument, in the context of Marx’s distinctiveness on these
issues compared to Burke and fascism, can be found in Mark Neocleous, The Monstrous
and the Dead (Cardiff, 2004).
60 Marx, Eighteenth Brumaire, p. 149.
61 Marx to Ruge, May 1843, in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works,
Vol. 3 (London, 1975), p. 134.
62 Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, The German Ideology (1846), in Karl Marx and
Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 5 (London, 1976), p. 137. Likewise: ‘The capitalist
gentlemen will never want for fresh exploitable flesh and blood, and will let the
dead bury their dead’—Karl Marx, ‘Wage Labour and Capital’ (1849), in Karl Marx and
Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 9 (London, 1977), p. 226.
63 Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Manifesto of the Communist Party (1848), in
Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 6 (London, 1976), p. 499.
64 Marx, Capital, p. 91.
65 Marx to Engels, 24 August 1867, Collected Works, Vol. 42 (London, 1987), p. 407.
66 Marx, ‘Wage Labour and Capital’, pp. 213, 215.
67 Marx, Capital, pp. 342, 989–90.
68 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 461.
69 Ibid., p. 364.
70 Marx, Capital, p. 289.
71 Baldick, In Frankenstein’s Shadow, p. 129.
72 Marx, ‘Wage Labour and Capital’, p. 228.
73 Marx, Capital, p. 376.
74 Ibid., p. 416.
75 Karl Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts (1844), in Early Writings,
trans. Rodney Livingstone and Gregor Benton (Harmondsworth, 1975), p. 324, emphasis
in original.
76 Ibid., p. 390, emphasis in original.
77 Cited in Marx and Engels, German Ideology, p. 104.
78 Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts, p. 352.
79 Ibid., p. 361.
80 Terry Eagleton, The Ideology of the Aesthetic (Oxford, 1990), p. 200.
81 Marx, Capital, p. 169, emphasis added.
82 Ibid., pp. 163–5.
83 Patrick Brantlinger, Fictions of State: Culture and Credit in Britain, 1694–1994
(Ithaca, NY, 1996), p. 148.
84 See here Slavoj Zizek, For They Know Not What They Do: Enjoyment as a Political
Factor (London, 1991), p. 221.
Mark Neocleous
Dept. of Politics, Brunel University, Uxbridge, UB8 3PH. Email: mark.neocleous
@brunel.ac.uk
HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT. Vol. XXIV. No. 4. Winter 2003
No comments:
Post a Comment